Book Review - Hitler's Justice: The Courts of the Third Reich
Rabbi Yitzchok Breitowitz
|
Book Review
Hitler's Justice: The Courts of the Third Reich by Ingo Muller
(translated by Deborah Lucas Schneider with introduction by Detlev Vagts)
(Harvard University Press, 1991)
Reviewed by Yitzchok A. Breitowitz, assistant professor of law
at the University of Maryland and Rabbi of the Woodside Synagogue
in Silver Spring.
Since the end of the World War II, many have wondered about the
roles of lawyers, judges, and law professors in Hitler's rise to
power and the role they continued to play for the duration of the
Third Reich. How could persons committed to the rule of law and
steeped in fundamental notions of due process and respect for
individual dignity become active participants in a regime of
lawlessness and unparalleled brutality? In the aftermath of the
war, there were a number of attempts made to justify or at least
excuse the conduct of the legal profession, the most prominent
of which was the work authored by Hubert Schorn, a former
County Judge. Schorn argued that: (1) judicial resistance to
the arbitrary edicts of the Reich was in fact widespread; (2)
judges were "victims" of their legal training which stressed
"positivism," a definition of law that was divorced from any moral
vision and which must be automatically obeyed and mechanically
applied; (3) judges were legitimately fearful of losing not only
their jobs but their lives and thus acted under duress; (4) judges
retained their position in the honest belief that they would be
better than any successors the Nazis would have chosen. Many
have noted the inconsistent strands of Schorn's argument (akin
to the criminal defendant who asserts both that he didn't commit
the crime and that he was forced into doing it through duress)
but his work provided virtually every jurist of the Nazi era
with a panoply of excuses to choose from. Still others maintain
that the Nazi regime was sui generis - a temporary
aberration that is disconnected from either the German past or
its present.
In 1987, Ingo Muller, an official in the Justice Department of
Bremen and a former law professor, published a meticulously
documented work in German which sought to demolish the widely
held Schorn thesis. In Hitler's Justice - which became a
best-seller in Germany - Muller convincingly argues that the extent
of active resistance was dismally small, that many jurists were
active collaborators in the worst excesses of the Nazi regime
beyond the call of duty or the limits of positivistic thinking,
and most shocking of all many of the offenders successfully
reintegrated themselves into the judicial system of West Germany.
He also argues that for from being an aberration, Nazi attitudes
were rooted in Weimar jurisprudence and to a large extent, survive
intact in the law today. Muller's book has now appeared in English,
lucidly translated by Deborah Lucas Schneider.
Coming on the heels of German reunification and shortly before
the formal reunification of Europe in 1992, it is perhaps not the
most auspicious time to reopen the painful old wounds of World
War II and the Holocaust yet Muller's work contains important
lessons and as George Santayana reminds us, those who don't learn
from history may be condemned to repeat it.
The book is divided into three parts. The first and shortest
portion of the book describes the judicial system that existed
under the Weimar Republic and demonstrates that, rather than being
an aberration, much of the jurisprudence of the Nazi era stemmed
directly from authoritarian attitudes prevalent among the educated
middle class in Weimar Germany and that were enthusiastically
embraced by its jurists and legal scholars.
The longest portion of the book describes the operation of the
German legal system from 1933 to the unconditional surrender to the
allied powers in 1945. In eighteen well-documented chapters, Muller
paints a terrifying portrait of a judicial and administrative system
where legal niceties are at least occasionally observed but where
decency and justice have ceased to exist-a nightmarish caricature
of law without moral value. Legalization of euthanasia and
sterilization, the creation of concentration camps, the ruthless
crushing of political opposition, the cancerous growth of racist
and anti-semitic laws labelling Jews as civilly-dead are introduced
in rapid succession with nary a word of protest from the lawyers
and judges who then proceed to apply the laws as routinely as one
would apply some technical provision of the Internal Revenue Code.
The death penalty was meted out for even trivial offenses if the
State (read: judge, read: the Nazi party) regarded the offense
as "undermining the security of the state" or the purity of the
Aryan race. Thus, Leo Katzenberger was executed for merely
maintaining a friendship with a German female tenant (pp. 113-115).
Nor was this persecution limited to Jews. Two Greeks, one 19
and the other 20, were shot for removing a pair of discarded
shoes from an abandoned bombed-out building (p. 169).
Where the Nazi regime could not obtain its desired results through
the official judicial system, it simply created special courts not
subject even on paper to the minimal constraints of due process.
The most infamous of these was the People's Court specializing in
expeditious justice against those who questioned the wisdom of the
Fuehrer (even if the "attack" was nothing more than a casual comment
made over the dinner table). When all else failed - and for
some reason an accused was acquitted, the doctrine of preventive
detention allowed for his immediate rearrest by the Gestapo on no
legal grounds at all. We read in astonishment that the Gestapo
would often arrest a person in the very courtroom in which he had
just been acquitted. To the extent this practice elicited protest,
the Gestapo was merely requested to wait until the defendant left
the room in order not to assault the dignity of the court (pp.
175-176). In a sense, being acquitted was even worse than a
conviction; while prison sentences had fixed terms, preventive
detention was functionally equivalent to a death sentence following
torture. Under the infamous "night and fog" decrees, persons
simply vanished without a trace and even their families were not
notified (pp. 170-173).
Basic notions of fundamental fairness in the enactment of criminal
legislation simply didn't exist. Ex post-facto laws were common;
people could be punished for acts that were not even criminal when
they were committed. Indeed, people could be punished even for acts
that were never made expressly criminal if such acts were "similar"
to those that were (doctrine of analogy in criminal law). The state
had the right to appeal an acquittal or what it regarded as a lenient
sentence. or it could simply forego the appeals route altogether and
invoke preventive detention. Contrary to the central idea that
conduct proscribed as criminal should be identified with specificity,
criminal statutes were often phrased in vague, general terms that
could, and often did, apply to virtually anything giving defendants
no advance warning that their conduct could be prosecutable. Rules
of evidence (at least on the prosecution side) were nil; defendants
were routinely convicted and even sentenced to death through
uncorroborated hearsay or guilt by association. (In one case, a
defendant was sentenced on the basis of out-of-court growling of a
dog) (p. 166). Nor was there any notion of a meaningful right to
counsel. Attorneys for the defense were regarded, and regarded
themselves, as agents of the state and would have no hesitation to
turn against their "client." Nor were these miscarriages of justice
limited to the sphere of criminal prosecution. Even routine cases
of contract, labor law, the issuance of drivers' licenses, and
child custody were permeated with the racist hatreds that were at
the core of National Socialist ideology.
Stories of Nazi brutality are of course nothing new. Indeed, one
might say that whatever perversions of justice occurred in the
operation of the courts pale into insignificance when compared to
the lawless brutality of the ghettos and concentration camps. Yet
there is a special significance and dimension to vignettes of
systemic judicial terror. First, we learn that the brutalistic Nazi
regime implemented its "crimes" not through sheer force alone but
through a patina of legality; statutes were duly enacted, regulations
drafted by competent and often talented legal technicians, judicial
opinions were carefully crafted all to explain and justify what
would otherwise be nothing more than state-sponsored terrorism.
Utilization of at least the rhetoric of the "rule of law" - in spite
of Hitler's own personal contempt for the concept and it
practitioners - served a vital legitimizing function for the Reich.
Legalism lent the Reich's excesses the appearance of respectability
and legality, a sense of continuity with the Weimar traditions of
the past, a sense of false comfort and security to the citizenry
that the reality of barbaric terror was in fact cabined by civilized
traditions and orderly procedures which at least externally bore
superficial resemblances to comparable institutions in other
countries and those that had previously existed in Germany itself.
This legitimation could well have been a potent psychological
factor in deluding the German people into accepting what was going
on. It was also an important first step; had Hitler been unable
to operate through the established legal institutions of the country
in all likelihood much of his program would have been nipped in
the bud. It was only by wresting control of the legal structure
that the Third Reich was ultimately able to ignore it. In short,
it may be surmised that without the cooperation and cooption of the
legal system, and its abrogation of individual rights under the
guise of law, none of the later brutalities could ever have been
tolerated or accepted. (Moreover, couching political and religious
persecution in "laws" and having those laws enforced through judicial
proceedings create a sense of bloodless abstraction - where the
application of a given statute becomes an exercise in technical
skill rather than the imposition of unjust suffering on a human
being - and this in turn could be partial explanation why so many
judges just did their job without ever considering just what it
was they were doing.)
Second, we like to think that civilization, a sophisticated legal
system and respect for the rule of law stand as firm bulwarks for
the protection of individual liberties against infringement by the
state. Yet Muller's book reminds us of the disheartening truth -
the fragility of even long-standing legal systems and the fact
that not only will they crack under stress but may in fact be
enlisted as a potent tool in the legitimation of oppression and
the powers of evil. Remember: the Nazis did what they did not
by ignoring law but by manipulating it.
Third, the book reminds us that contrary to the self-serving
assertions of postwar jurists, the extent of resistance to the Nazi
terror on the part of the legal profession was minuscule. While
many jurists were removed and executed because they were Jewish and
other judges resigned in protest over attacks on their pension
rights, Muller claims that only one jurist officially protested
Nazi injustices and was forced to take early retirement (pp.
193-197). Nor is it wholly true that jurists were simply "victims"
of their "positivistic" orientation to mechanically follow and
apply the law. While legal positivism may well have contributed
to a psychological detachment from the antisocial consequences of
their rulings and in an emotional sense may have made it easier
for judges to live with their consciences, their creative and
enthusiastic application of Nazi doctrine was closer in many
cases to active and coequal collaboration than to passive
acquiescence. It is also argued that jurists had no meaningful
choice; resisting National Socialism would not only have cost
them their careers but their lives as well. It is significant,
however, that in the one case of recorded resistance, that of
Kreyssig early retirement was all that was required and if many
more judges had truly protested the tenets of Nazism, one wonders
whether Hitler, at least in the early years of the Reich, would
have had the effrontery to even dismiss them.
Undoubtedly, Muller paints with a fairly broad brush. Certainly,
there were many judges who openly and enthusiastically embraced
the racist tenets of National Socialism. Witness the performance
of Roland Freisler, the President of the People's Court whose
rantings were so offensive that the Nazis themselves refused to
release a film of his proceedings originally made for public
relations purposes (p. 150). Others, equally if not more culpable,
were rank opportunists willing to jump on any bandwagon to advance
their careers (pp. 41-45). Others may indeed have adopted a stance
of relative passivity out of sheer fear and yet a final group went
around their business in corporate and commercial law with little
or no daily involvement in racist/Aryan policies. While members
of the legal profession are not all equally culpable, the message
that emerges from Muller's book is crystal-clear. Neither the
bar nor the judiciary made any organized attempts to oppose
any aspects of Hitler's regime; the bar and judiciary as
bodies heartily endorsed racial exclusionary policies; the number
of individual resisters was extremely small. The very best that
can be said for the legal profession is that they had no impact
in stopping Nazism and in all likelihood, had complicity in its
growth. The choice is between impotence and culpability - they
were certainly not an active force for good.
The question that Muller does not answer, and on which we can only
speculate, is whether widespread legal resistance would have made
a difference. On one level, of course, the answer may be irrelevant.
The duty to oppose evil does not depend on any calculus of success.
On another level, I would submit that resistance may very well have
been effective. Particularly in the early years of the Reich, the
1935-1936 period when Hitler was still consolidating his power, the
legitimation of his decrees by the courts and the legal profession
was a crucial element in extending the government's authority.
Each small victory, each incursion into personal liberties without
protest enabled Nazism to extend its insidious tentacles further.
The policy of appeasement in domestic affairs worked as effectively
as it later did in the area of foreign policy with the same disastrous
results. Perhaps more so than for any other segment of German society,
the judiciary's abdication of responsibility was not only a personal
moral failure but a catastrophe for the world at large. (Again,
however, I speak from hindsight - if anything, this should teach us
to be vigilant about our own liberties).
The third part of the book focuses on the aftermath and here, the
author presents us with a number of shocking conclusions. Despite
the wavering, half-hearted attempts at the de-Nazification that the
allied powers sought to impose on post-war Germany, many jurists
with strong affiliations to Nazism were reinstated and in many
cases promoted. Initial postwar appointments of opponents of the
Reich were later rescinded on the grounds of disloyalty to the
state while faithful civil servants of the 1933-1945 period were
given priority in hiring. To take one extreme example, an S.S.
trooper involved in atrocities against the Jews in the Ukraine
turns up again 25 years later issuing rulings against Communists
and student protestors (p. 217). A former Nazi winds up as head
of the Central Office of State Administration for the Prosecution
of National Socialist Crimes and served in that capabity for six
years (p. 215).
Perhaps even more disturbing than continuity of personnel - which
due to the numbers of Germans pledging allegiance to Nazism was
essentially an administrative necessity - are the strong undercurrents
of hostility found in many judicial decisions against opponents
of the Reich; the continuing insistence of the courts that actions
taken pursuant to the laws of the Reich were "legal" in accepting
the defense of legal necessity; and in the refusal of the
Bundestag to this very day to set aside the judicial decisions of
the Nazi era, even those of the infamous People's Court. Muller
also demonstrates how postwar courts have shown remarkable
solicitude and forgiveness for the administrators of Nazi justice
while taking an unusually hard-line on other radical groups.
Victims received little or nothing through the postwar judicial
system while perpetrators continued unscathed through retirement
or natural death. Finally, much of the legislation currently on
the books embody racial concepts drawn directly from National
Socialist policy with only cosmetic changes.
In short, Muller has presented us with a profoundly-troubling book,
but an important one - a work that invites pensive reflection on
what might have been; a work that reminds us how fragile a legal
system is against the powers of darkness; a work that teaches us
that civilization, culture, and an ostensible commitment to and
tradition of the rule of law are at best frail barriers against the
onslaught of tyranny and how moral courage is a rare commodity in
any age. He also reminds us that Nazism was not an anomalous virus
coming down from outer space but was part and parcel of the German
legal culture that preceded 1933 and continues to have echoes that
reverberate in 1991, echoes that have not yet been dissipated or
erased.
The author has taken well-defined positions on a sharply-debated
and controversial period of modern history and indeed, as previously
noted sometimes overstates his case. He fails to acknowledge, for
example, the West German reparations policy nor does he mention East
Germany's fairly radical purging of Nazi elements from its
government. Some of his readings of current West German legislation
seem unduly condemnatory, particularly in view of West German's strong
rules against Neo-Nazi propaganda and its renewed commitment to
human rights. The book preceded such recent conciliatory (although
largely symbolic) gestures as the formal apologies by East Germany
and Austria for atrocities committed during the Holocaust (though
technically these do not involve West Germany). On balance,
however, Muller's points are well-documented and worthy of our
careful consideration and scrutiny.
Note should also be taken of the very helpful introduction and
bibliography authored by Detlev Vagts who, although unidentified
in the book, is a Professor of Law at Harvard University and a
well-known expert in comparative law. Vagts lays out the precise
areas of historical debate, qualifies some of Muller's generalizations,
and provides suggestions for further reading.
|