How School Vouchers Can Win In The Supreme Court - Distinguishing 'What' From
'How' In Aid To Religious Schools
Nathan Lewin |
How
School Vouchers Can Win In The Supreme Court - Distinguishing 'What' From 'How' in Aid To
Religious Schools
Nathan Lewin
(Continuation)
From page one
Perhaps the most formidable obstacle to programs that provide aid to students in
religious schools has been the three-pronged "Lemon test." As was noted
at the outset of this paper, the Court purported in Lemon to synthesize the
"cumulative criteria developed by the Court over many years" into a
three-pronged analytical test for programs challenged as unconstitutional
"establishments" of religion: (1) The challenged statute or program must have a
secular legislative purpose; (2) its "principal or primary effect" must be one
that "neither advances nor inhibits religion"; and (3) it must not result in
"excessive government entanglement with religion." 403 U.S. at 612-613.
The first "prong" has always proved easy for aid-to-religious-school programs
to satisfy. In case after case Lemon, Nyquist, Meek, Wolman
programs have foundered against the second and third parts of the test. In the
opinion of many commentators and, indeed, several Justices, the Lemon
"test" is not a test at all, but is actually an after-the-fact rationale
employed by the Court to justify the result it chooses for other reasons, including a
flimsily masked antipathy on the part of several Justices toward religious schools. As
Justice Antonin Scalia has remarked, "[w]hen we wish to strike down a practice [the Lemon
test] forbids, we invoke it, . . . when we wish to uphold a practice it forbids, we ignore
it entirely." Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School District,
508 U.S. 384, 399 (1993) (concurring opinion).
Even in post-Lemon cases where the Court has upheld aid to religious schools, it
has nonetheless felt obliged to march through the tests three steps. Thus, in Mueller,
Justice Rehnquist discussed the fact that benefits under the challenged aid program were
available directly to all parents, on the basis of neutral criteria, whether their
children attended public, private, or religious schools, and so concluded that the program
satisfied the "primary effect" prong of the Lemon test. 463 U.S. at
396-402. And Justice Marshall, in upholding Mr. Witters use of state aid in his
religious studies, also labored to structure his reasoning around the tests three
prongs. Of course, on the same facts, different sets of Justices might well have concluded
otherwise in both these cases. "Primary effect" and "excessive
entanglement" are, it seems, in the eye of the beholder.
Today, however, the status of the Lemon test is not so clear. The case continues
to be cited, but many have concluded that "Lemon is dead." There is ample
support for this view. In Lee v. Weisman, 505 U.S. 577 (1992), the Court held
unconstitutional, as an establishment of religion, a nondenominational prayer at a high
school graduation, without applying Lemon. Nor did Chief Justice Rehnquist apply or
even cite the test in Zobrest. Instead, he simply concluded that the program in
that case was more like those upheld in Witters and Mueller than like those
struck down in Ball, Meek, and Nyquist. The Court did apply the Lemon
test, albeit perfunctorily and in one sentence, that same year in Lambs Chapel v.
Center Moriches Union Free School District, 508 U.S. 384 (1993), holding that a public
school district could not deny a church group access to a public schools facilities
for the purpose of a religious film series. 508 U.S. at 395. This prompted Justice Scalia
to make the earlier quoted comparison of Lemon to a "ghoul in a late-night
horror movie." 508 U.S. at 398 (concurring opinion).
In Agostini v. Felton, the Court majority did not exorcise the Lemon
ghoul, but it did at least hack off one of its limbs. The question whether a program
creates an "excessive entanglement" between government and religion has
apparently been demoted in status, from a separate "prong" of the test to a mere
"aspect" of the inquiry into the programs "effect." An
"excessive entanglement" is now one that has the "effect" of
"advanc[ing] or inhibit[ing] religion." 117 S. Ct. at 2015. Agostini was,
to be sure, a close 5-to-4 decision, and the last 50 years have shown that much of the
Courts jurisprudence in this area depends on the particular Justices in any given
majority. But even Justice Souter, who wrote the dissent in Agostini, did not feel
the need to argue that New Yorks Title I program violated the Lemon test.
Instead, he contended that the program violated "two central tenets of Establishment
Clause jurisprudence" by "subsidiz[ing] religion directly" and by acting
"in a way that could reasonably be viewed as religious endorsement." 117 S. Ct.
at 2020 (dissenting opinion).
Agostini was a missed opportunity for the Supreme Court. It could have interred Lemon
once and for all, but it failed to do so. A reasonable observer reading Agostini
could conclude that the Lemon test is no longer a meaningful gauge of how the
Supreme Court will decide a particular case and surely not a useful test for
arguing the constitutionality of a voucher program. Nonetheless, the conventions of
constitutional law require that the Lemon test be addressed in briefs and oral
argument in any case involving Establishment Clause issues.
This overview of Supreme Court cases reveals that the programs providing public aid to
religious schools considered by the Supreme Court over the past 50 years have relied on
two discrete constitutional theories:
The first approach, illustrated by the Everson, Allen, and Tilton
cases, focused on the nature of the activity that was financed or, putting it in a
slightly different way, on the content of the government aid. For example, when a
school district decides to reimburse parents for the cost of bus transportation or to loan
secular textbooks to students attending religious schools, public funds are necessarily
used only to support conduct that is incontestably secular. Such services are
"self-policing, in that starting as secular, nonideological and neutral, they will
not change in use." Meek, 421 U.S. at 365. The contents of a particular
secular textbook are fixed; the book remains a secular book no matter where or by whom it
is read. To the extent that the Establishment Clause prohibits public funds to be spent on
religious activity or teaching, the government agency can defend its payments for bus
transportation or its purchase of secular books loaned to religious schools because no
public money is being spent "for religion." Rather, the funds are being used to
purchase incontestably secular services and materials.
To be sure, an argument can be made and it often is that by relieving the
religious school of its own need to purchase these secular services, the government
agency frees up the religious schools money for the purchase of materials or
services needed for religious instruction, materials that, it is assumed, the government
could not purchase directly. See, e.g., Ball, 473 U.S. at 396-397; Meek,
421 U.S. at 365-366; Nyquist, 413 U.S. at 775. But this claim that there is
an indirect benefit provided to religion whenever the government pays for a significant
part of a religious schools secular program or activity rests on the dubious
assumption that the government may not provide an indirect benefit to religion. The Court
has regularly rejected the sweeping argument that any indirect benefit to religion
violates the Establishment Clause. As the Court noted nearly 50 years ago in Everson,
the possibility of indirect benefit to religious schools exists whenever, for example, a
policeman protects children walking to and from religious schools and a city hauls away a
churchs trash. 330 U.S. at 17. The Court reaffirmed this point in Zobrest,
509 U.S. at 8 (quoting Widmar v. Vincent, 487 U.S. 589, 609 (1988)): "[I]f the
Establishment Clause did bar religious groups from receiving general government benefits,
then a church could not be protected by the police and fire departments, or have its
public sidewalk kept in repair." Money, after all, is fungible, and any time a
religious organization receives the benefit of any public service, it is spared the
expense of providing that service for itself and it has that much more money available for
its religious mission.
This first approach to assisting children in religious schools emphasizes what
the program provides i.e., the nature or content of the service purchased
with public funds. After the apparent success of this approach in Everson and Allen,
advocates of aid to religious schools sought to finance with public funds the salaries of
teachers in religious schools who taught secular subjects, as well as the purchase of
textbooks, maps, lab equipment, and other counseling services. These advocates argued
that, as in those earlier cases, the nature and content of the aid sought was, without
dispute, secular.
In Lemon, Nyquist, Meek, and Wolman, the Court rejected
this approach. Instead, applying the "Lemon test," the Court asked
whether, notwithstanding the secular content of the government benefits themselves, they
nonetheless might have the "effect" of furthering the religious mission of the
parochial school. The Court based its decisions in these cases not on the nature of the
aid itself, but on the potential for indirect advancement of religion, indoctrination by
the teachers of secular subjects, "political divisiveness," and
"entanglement." This kind of analysis, of course, is likely to be and has
proved to be far less predictable and consistent, and much more dependent on the
Justices subjective impressions, than a straightforward focus on the content of the
aid provided to a religious school or the nature of the activity subsidized. As the Court
acknowledged in Lemon and as was confirmed by the inconsistency and
unpredictability of later decisions, "[c]andor compels acknowledgement . . . that we
can only dimly perceive the lines of demarcation in this extraordinarily sensitive area of
constitutional law." 403 U.S. at 612.
The second approach considered by the Court and pressed by religious-school advocates
does not focus on the nature or content of the aid itself and does not limit the use of
secular goods or services. Instead, public money was allocated that could benefit
religious schools directly and might even be used to purchase or subsidize unabashedly
religious services, books, or materials. The constitutional key to these programs, though,
is that any benefit to religious institutions or to religion generally results from
"genuinely independent and private choice." The constitutional theory underlying
these programs is that the benefit conferred on a religious school is not being conferred
by government. Instead, government remains neutral, and disburses public funds to private
individuals, earmarked for a particular public-welfare purpose like education. Private
individuals then determine where the money is to be spent. Todays school-choice and
voucher proposals represent an example of this second approach.
Although Allen and Everson contained the seeds of this second approach
the bus services and textbooks were provided to all schoolchildren, and it
was therefore a matter of private choice whether public funds ended up being used in
religious schools the first clear example of this approach considered by the Court
was the tuition-reimbursement and tax-credit program struck down by the Court in Nyquist.
The Supreme Court invalidated the program and did not deem it significant that
parents choices, not government choices, determined whether these programs
benefits would be used at religious or secular nonpublic schools.
The New York program, however, was a flawed example of the second approach because it
was constitutionally "underinclusive" in failing to provide similar tax relief
for parents of children attending public schools. The Minnesota tax legislation
that was challenged in Mueller v. Allen filled this gap and therefore passed
Supreme Court scrutiny. The Court, in upholding the Minnesota program, was not troubled,
as the Court in Nyquist had been, by the fact that public money might end up having
"an economic effect comparable to that of aid given directly to the schools."
463 U.S. at 399. In fact, the Court recognized that the vast majority of the benefits
conferred under the program would, as a practical matter, end up in religious
schools. What was more important to the Court in keeping with the constitutional
theory of this second approach was that "public funds become available [to
religious schools] only as a result of numerous private choices of individual parents of
school-age children." 463 U.S. at 399. To the question why the result in Mueller
was different than in Nyquist, despite the fact that in both cases involved aid to
parents, not schools, Justice Rehnquist answered, "[m]ost importantly, the deduction
[was] available for educational expenses incurred by all parents, including those
whose children attend public schools and those whose children attend nonsectarian private
schools or sectarian private schools." 463 U.S. at 397.
In Mueller we see at work a different constitutional theory than that which
underlies payment for bus transportation, loaned textbooks, school lunches, instructional
materials, and building-construction grants. The program in Mueller was
constitutional not because of what was purchased with public funds but because of how
the public funds reached the beneficiary. Under this theory, the Constitution is not
violated because the money has been directed to its final goal by a private agent, not by
a state official.
The Courts decision in Mueller, and its apparent acceptance of this second
approach, explains the result in both Witters and Zobrest. These cases
involved expenditures for services that were unquestionably religious in nature. In Witters
a blind student was permitted to use public funds to study to be a pastor, and in Zobrest,
a deaf student in a Catholic school was provided an interpreter, with government money,
even in his religion classes. The Court upheld the aid in both cases although each
involved a disbursement of public funds. Furthermore, both the Nyquist tax-credit
plan and the Mueller tax deduction had only consequential and circuitous impacts on
the public treasury. Taxpayers benefited by reduced tax bills, and it was anticipated that
the religious schools would then demand increased payments from the taxpayer-parents to
their tax advantages. Witters and Zobrest, however, extended the
constitutional theory of Mueller to the area of affirmative government grants. Mr.
Witters was permitted to spend government money to buy a religious education, and the
parents of James Zobrest were empowered to have public funds spent for an interpreter at a
Catholic parochial school. As a result of private choice, the government-sponsored
interpreter communicated to the child the context of the schools religious
curriculum as well as its secular teaching. The Courts view of the matter was clear:
"James parents have chosen of their own free will to place him in a pervasively
sectarian environment. The sign-language interpreter they have requested will neither add
to nor subtract from that environment, and hence the provision of such assistance is not
barred by the Establishment Clause." Zobrest, 509 U.S. at 13.
The Supreme Courts decisions concerning aid to religious schools highlight the
important distinction between (1) public-funding programs that limit what may be
purchased with government money and (2) public-funding programs that prescribe how
government money reaches private beneficiaries. Various efforts along the first of these
lines to shape and structure programs funding only secular activities were rebuffed by the
Supreme Court in a series of decisions issued in the 1970s and 1980s. Although many of
those cases were wrongly decided, they form the constitutional landscape and cannot be
ignored in considering constitutional strategy. By contrast, programs that provide
unrestricted public funding to private religious schools as a result of designations by
private individuals have proved increasingly successful in the Supreme Court in recent
years. Todays school-voucher programs and proposals naturally fall into the latter
category, and there are positive signs in recent Supreme Court opinions, and in the work
of leading First Amendment theorists, that justify optimism regarding the
constitutionality of such programs.
Agostini is the latest in a series of cases, including Mueller, Zobrest,
and Witters, indicating that a well-drafted school-voucher proposal would be found
constitutional because the proposal would revolve around the manner by which public
funds are channeled to religious schools that is, it would empower parents to make
"independent private choices" to send their children to religious schools. The
crucial question for advocates of school vouchers is whether the Supreme Court or,
more precisely, a majority of the current Justices would accept the premise that a
school-voucher program, like the programs at issue in the Mueller-Witters-Zobrest-Agostini
line of cases, really interposes "genuinely independent and private choices"
between the disbursal of funds from the public treasury and the religious school that is
the eventual beneficiary of those funds.
When discussing this crucial concept of intervening and independent private choice, the
Supreme Court has several times invoked, for purposes of comparison and illustration, a
hypothetical model which it apparently views as an example of an unquestionably
constitutional transfer of public funds to a religious institution. The model is a
charitable contribution made by a government employee to his church. In Witters,
Justice Thurgood Marshall considered the "effect" of the challenged government
aid in the following terms (474 U.S. at 486-487):
It is well settled that the Establishment Clause is not violated every time money
previously in the possession of a State is conveyed to a religious institution. For
example, a State may issue a paycheck to one of its employees, who may then donate all or
part of that paycheck to a religious institution, all without constitutional barrier; and
the State may do so even knowing that the employee so intends to dispose of his salary. .
. . The question presented is whether . . . extension of aid to petitioner and the use of
that aid by petitioner to support his religious education is a permissible transfer
similar to the hypothetical salary donation described above, or is an impermissible
"direct subsidy."
The Court majority endorsed this same analogy just last year in Agostini v. Felton,
117 S. Ct. at 2011-2012:
The grants [at issue in Witters] were disbursed directly to students, who then
used the money to pay for tuition at the educational institution of their choice. In our
view, this transaction was no different from a States issuing a paycheck to one of
its employees, knowing that the employee would donate part or all of the check to a
religious institution. In both situations, any money that ultimately went to religious
institutions did so "only as a result of the genuinely independent and private
choices of" individuals. The same logic applied in Zobrest . . . .
This comparison with a government employees "hypothetical salary
donation" (Witters, 474 U.S. at 487) to a church or synagogue is a helpful
analytical device, as well as an important constitutional touchstone for voucher programs,
particularly in light of the confusion that so often plagues the Courts
jurisprudence in this area. If payments made to a religious school pursuant to a
parents use of an educational voucher are substantially equivalent to a government
employees voluntary charitable contribution, a school-voucher program should
withstand constitutional challenge. If, on the other hand, the use of a voucher payment
differs significantly from the "independent private choice" of a government
employees contribution, the school-choice program may be in serious trouble. It is,
therefore, useful to consider how the parents choice under a voucher system compares
with the "independent private choice" at work in Justice Marshalls
hypothetical charitable contribution.
The Court observed in Witters that the money directed by Mr. Witters to the
religious institution was "paid directly to the student, who transmits it to the
educational institution of his or her choice." 474 U.S. at 487. This fact may seem to
be a formalistic triviality (indeed, in earlier cases the Supreme Court has treated it as
such, see Nyquist, 413 U.S. at 781; Wolman, 433 U.S. at 250) but it is
essential to the charitable-contribution analogy. If a parent receives a government check
and is then authorized to endorse that check (or pay its proceeds) to any school he or she
chooses, the parent is comparable to the employee in Justice Marshalls
charitable-donation hypothetical. If, on the other hand, funds are paid directly from the
state treasury to the selected school be it religious or secular according
to the parents designation, it may not at least formally be the same
as the personal donation. The State, after all, is in the latter case more
"directly" involved in transmitting the funds to their eventual recipient.
Should this "formalistic" distinction make a difference?
Common sense suggests that it should not. The funds in question belong to the
individual, who simply designates an alternate payee the school of his or her
choice. It remains true that it is the individuals own choice about what to do with
his or her grant proceeds that determines where the money ultimately goes. The government
does not itself make the choice to pay the religious school. The Court acknowledged as
much in Zobrest, noting that "there would be no problem under the
Establishment Clause if the [funds] instead went directly to [the students] parents,
who, in turn, hired the interpreter themselves." 509 U.S. at 13 & n.11. Just as
the Constitution permits government to disburse public-welfare benefits to a private
individual who, in turn, spends those funds for a religious purpose, it permits government
to direct benefits for use in a religious school at the request of an eligible private
beneficiary.
A real-world example, familiar to any federal employee, illustrates this point. Each
year, as part of the Combined Federal Campaign, federal employees are given the
opportunity to designate that a portion of their paychecks be sent by the government to
charitable and non-profit organizations. This program is widely viewed as a way of
encouraging charitable giving a secular interest, presumably. Hundreds of these
non-profit organizations are overtly religious. No one thinks that when the federal
government acts in accord with its employees wishes and sends a portion of the
employees paycheck to a religious organization, it has thereby undertaken to
subsidize religion.
The governments money disbursed under a school-voucher program may be used only
for tuition or other school expenses. A voucher is not simply "free money," and
a parent is not at liberty to use the funds he or she receives from the public treasury to
pay for groceries, medical bills, or vacation trips. In this regard, however, an
educational voucher is plainly different from the salary received by a government
employee, who is, of course, free to make any (legal) use he or she wishes of his earned
paycheck.
But that difference does not appear to be constitutionally dispositive, as is
demonstrated by the Witters case. The allocation involved in Witters was
exactly like a school-voucher program. The funds provided by the state agency could only
be used "for special education and/or training." 474 U.S. at 483. The money
could not be spent on groceries, medical care, lottery tickets, or any other
personal purpose. Nonetheless, the Supreme Court unanimously found that Mr. Witters
use of these funds for a religious education was constitutionally permissible. Similarly,
the particular tax deduction at issue in Mueller was available only for educational
expenses (although, of course, as in any state, similar deductions were available for
other enumerated expenses), and the IDEA funds to which James Zobrest was entitled could
only be used for special-education-related expenses.
The tuition-reimbursement and tax-credit benefits in Nyquist were only available
to parents whose children were attending nonpublic schools. In Witters, however,
Justice Marshall observed quoting from Nyquists famous "footnote
38" that the funds for vocational rehabilitation at issue in that case were
"made available generally without regard to the sectarian-nonsectarian, or
public-nonpublic nature of the institution benefited." 474 U.S. at 487. The Court has
emphasized this same point in many other cases as well. In Allen, New York loaned
secular textbooks to all children, including those in religious schools. 392 U.S.
at 238. Everson involved reimbursement for public-transportation costs to all
parents. 330 U.S. at 17. The construction grants at issue in Tilton were available
to all qualifying universities and colleges. 403 U.S. at 675. Minnesota provided all
parents with a tax deduction for education-related expenses. Mueller, 463 U.S. at
397. And, most recently, the Court observed in Agostini that "[t]he services
are available to all children, no matter what their religious beliefs or where they go to
school." 117 S. Ct. at 2014. Given these precedents, a school-choice program should
provide that vouchers can be used in public, private, or religious schools.
Californias Proposition 174 was an example of such a program, as is the
school-choice program currently in place in Cleveland, Ohio. Proposition 174 offered an
"educational scholarship" for every resident, school-age child in the State.
These scholarships could have been redeemed at any participating school public,
private, or religious that met certain non-discrimination requirements. Similarly,
in Cleveland, both private schools and public schools in adjoining communities are
eligible to participate in the choice program.
This question follows naturally from the previous one. Just as the
employer-contribution analogy suggests that a voucher program should include
government-run as well as private schools, it would also require that parents be given the
same amount of money, or the same benefit, whether their child attends a religious or
secular school. In Witters, Justice Marshall emphasized that Washingtons aid
program was "in no way skewed towards religion," "create[d] no financial
incentive for students to undertake sectarian education," and "did not tend to
provide greater or broader benefits for recipients who apply their aid to religious
education, nor are the full benefits of the program limited, in large part or in whole, to
students at sectarian institutions." 474 U.S. at 487-88. The Court has made the same
point in other cases as well. See, e.g., Zobrest, 509 U.S. at 10; Agostini,
117 S. Ct. at 2014. These features, the Witters Court reasoned, distinguished
Washingtons program from the program struck down in Nyquist. And these
features are also important to Justice Marshalls government-employee analogy. An
employee who chooses to make religious organizations the object of his charity is not paid
more than those who prefer secular charities.
To be sure, more parents may choose to give their children a religious education in
religious schools if there is a voucher program than do now. This is because
parochial-school expenses that have heretofore been borne totally by the parents will,
under a voucher program, be partly defrayed by public funds. Choosing a religious school
becomes, for many low-income parents especially, a more feasible option. But this merely
places religion on a more even keel with non-religion. It does not tip the scales or
"skew" the balance in favor of religion. Indeed, putting parents in a financial
position where their choice between religious schools and secular ones can be made not on
the basis of money, but on the basis of religious belief and educational philosophy,
simply increases citizens freedoms. Hence the voucher program equalizes opportunity,
rather than "skews toward religion."
The right question is not whether more parents may choose to send their children to
religious school. It is, rather, whether the program itself creates an
"incentive" to use ones voucher-created power of choice to attend a
religious school. Under the voucher programs own criteria and terms is the religious
option more appealing? In Agostini, the Court explained that it was not a
"financial incentive to undertake religious indoctrination" if "the aid is
allocated on the basis of neutral, secular criteria that neither favor nor disfavor
religion, and is made available to both religious and secular beneficiaries on a
nondiscriminatory basis." 117 S. Ct. at 2014. The same was true in Witters,
where the Court clarified what it meant when it noted that the program was not
"skewed toward religion" by adding that the program did not provide greater
benefits to those who chose religious schools. 474 U.S. at 488. As the Court observed in
both Agostini and in Mueller, the Constitution does not judge an aid program
based on the number of students who use benefits, available under a facially neutral law,
to attend religious schools. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2013; Mueller, 463 U.S.
at 401.
Demonstrating what can only be characterized as a suspicious and hostile attitude
towards religious schools, the Court in Nyquist had warned against "ingenious
plans for channeling state aid to sectarian schools." 413 U.S. at 785. Justice
Marshall quoted this passage in Witters and noted that the Washington program of
providing educational assistance to the disabled was also not a covert vehicle for
subsidizing religious education. 474 U.S. at 487-488. The programs objective,
rather, was to assist those with vocational handicaps. Religious institutions were aided
only as an incident to the accomplishment of that objective. The same could be said of the
program that was at issue in Zobrest. Congress and the Arizona public authorities
wanted to help persons with disabilities. Religious belief and religious institutions were
only the secondary beneficiaries of the program designed to assist disabled people. The
Court said in Zobrest (509 U.S. at 12):
Disabled children, not sectarian schools, are the primary beneficiaries of the
[Individuals with Disabilities Education Act]; to the extent sectarian schools benefit at
all from the IDEA, they are only incidental beneficiaries. Thus the function of the IDEA
is hardly to "provide desired financial support for nonpublic, sectarian
institutions." Witters, 474 U.S. at 488 (quoting Nyquist, 413
U.S. at 783).
Similarly, the purpose of the textbook-loan program in Allen was the
"furtherance of the educational opportunities available to the young." 392 U.S.
at 243. And in Mueller the Court easily concluded that "a States efforts
to assist parents in meeting the rising cost of educational expenses plainly serves [the]
secular purpose of ensuring that the States citizenry is well educated." 463
U.S. at 395.
This is an important point for religious-school advocates. In a way, the question
whether a voucher program is designed "to provide desired financial support for
nonpublic, sectarian institutions" is the same as the first "prong" of the Lemon
test, which asks whether the program has a "secular legislative purpose." 403
U.S. at 612. It cannot be denied that, in addition to the some of the generic, secular
purposes just described, at least one consideration motivating those promoting
school-choice programs has been to help religious schools, even if only to promote
educational diversity or to ensure some kind of viable competition for government-run
schools. Indeed, this fact has often been highlighted by opponents of school choice. If
such a purpose irretrievably taints, for constitutional purposes, the result of
religious-school advocates lobbying efforts, then it is hard to see how a program
endorsed by religious organizations could ever pass constitutional muster. Fortunately,
the Court has stated that it will "only invalidate a statute [under the Establishment
Clause] if it is motivated wholly by an impermissible purpose." Bowen v. Kendrick,
487 U.S. 589, 602 (1988).
Additionally, the Supreme Court has repeatedly rejected the suggestion that an
otherwise valid law becomes unconstitutional under the Establishment Clause simply because
it happens to coincide with the legislative objectives of a church, or with the tenets of
a particular religion. The Court in Bowen v. Kendrick held that the Adolescent
Family Life Act, which authorized federal grants to agencies including religious
institutions that provided services aimed at reducing teenage pregnancy, was
constitutional on its face. It was not a fatal flaw that the Acts supporters were
motivated by religious concerns, and that Congress was aware of this fact. 487 U.S. at
602, 604 n. 9. The Court stated, "We see no reason to conclude that [the Act] serves
an impermissible religious purpose simply because some of the goals of the statute
coincide with the beliefs of certain religious organizations." 487 U.S. at 604 n. 8.
Obviously, a contrary rule would be impossible to administer, given that hundreds of
government programs and policies are consonant with, and may be prompted by, many
peoples religious beliefs. As the Court put it in McGowan v. Maryland, 366
U.S. 420, 442 (1961):
[T]he "Establishment" Clause does not ban federal or state regulation of
conduct whose reason or effect merely happens to coincide or harmonize with the tenets of
some or all religions. In many instances, the Congress or state legislatures conclude that
the general welfare of society, wholly apart from any religious considerations, demands
such regulation. Thus, for temporal purposes, murder is illegal. And that the fact that
this agrees with the dictates of the Judeo-Christian religions while it may disagree with
others does not invalidate the regulation. . . . The same could be said of theft, fraud,
etc., because those offenses were also proscribed in the Decalogue.
In invoking the charitable-contribution model, it is interesting that the Supreme Court
has never discussed or even noted one obvious distinction between its hypothetical and all
the public-funding programs that have been and are being litigated: The
government-employee contribution has, it is fair to assume, "earned" his or her
salary check. The government is not providing a gratuity when money that was once public
is, after being earned by the employee, directed by him or her to a religious institution.
It is hard to quarrel with the argument that the public treasury (and, by extension, a
potentially objecting taxpayer) is not harmed if the government employee exchanges his or
her labor for a check that is eventually signed over to a church or religious institution.
The beneficiary under any public-funding program is, on the other hand, receiving
government largesse when he like Larry Witters or James Zobrest personally
benefits from services that he purchases with government funds. A unilateral payment, or
benefits received under an entitlement program, depletes the public treasury with the
government appearing to receive nothing in return.
But this possible difference between vouchers and salary did not trouble Justice
Marshall in Witters. Nor was it even mentioned by the majority in Agostinis
recent discussion of Witters. The Supreme Court apparently does not view
social-welfare payments as government gratuities. Instead, it seems ready to treat such
payments as comparable to a payment of salary. A voucher for which a parent is eligible
according to statutory criteria "belongs" to that parent, as long as the statute
is in effect, just as surely as does that parents paycheck. The fact that James
Zobrests parents could sue government officials, demanding the benefits to which
they were entitled under the law, proves this point. Although a voucher is not
"earned" by the recipient, this should not be a serious obstacle to a
determination that a school-choice plan is constitutional.
All of the Supreme Court Justices agree that a government employee can donate his
paycheck to his church without violating the Constitution. It does not matter, for
constitutional purposes, that money that was once in the hands of the government ends up
via religiously motivated, but entirely private individual choice being put
to a religious use. Such choices are permitted by the Constitution. An important legal and
rhetorical challenge for school-choice advocates is to identify and highlight the
parallels between charitable contributions and vouchers.
Continued.
|