How School Vouchers Can Win In The Supreme Court - Distinguishing 'What' From
'How' In Aid To Religious Schools
Nathan Lewin |
How
School Vouchers Can Win In The Supreme Court - Distinguishing 'What' From 'How' in Aid To
Religious Schools
Nathan Lewin
(Continuation)
From page two.
Even if a voucher program passed the "test" of comparability to the private
charitable contributions of government employees, it could nonetheless run up against two
other obstacles created by the language of the most relevant Supreme Court decisions.
If the government gives a parent a voucher, and that parent uses the voucher in paying
for the tuition of his or her child at a religious school, the government has relieved
that parent of a cost he or she otherwise would have borne. For the reasons discussed
above, recent Supreme Court opinions emphasizing the importance of individual private
choice suggest that this fact does not itself make a voucher program unconstitutional.
Some cases, however, have raised a related problem by asking whether a particular aid
program relieves the school of costs it otherwise would have borne. In Zobrest,
for example, the Supreme Court emphasized the fact that government funding of a
sign-language interpreter for a deaf student attending a Catholic school did not relieve
sectarian schools "of costs they otherwise would have borne in educating their
students." 509 U.S. at 12. That is, were it not for the government assistance, the
deaf students parents, not the Catholic school, would have hired the interpreter.
The government had saved the parents some money as an incident of assisting the student.
It had not, however, subsidized the curriculum of the religious school or lifted an
economic burden that the school otherwise would have shouldered.
Contrast this situation with the Courts appraisal of the programs at issue in
cases like Meek and Ball. In Meek, the Court concluded that by
providing teaching material and equipment the State had relieved religious schools of an
otherwise necessary cost of performing their educational function. Even if the material
and equipment itself was secular, the aid "necessarily result[ed] in aid to the
sectarian school enterprise as a whole." 421 U.S. at 366. The same was true in Ball,
where the Court held that providing teachers, instructional material, and equipment to
religious schools was "indistinguishable from the provision of a direct cash subsidy
to the religious schools." 473 U.S. at 395. Even in Agostini, the Court felt
compelled to explain why it was "not persuaded that Title I services supplant the
remedial instruction and guidance already provided by New York Citys sectarian
schools." 117 S. Ct. 2013.
Vouchers are, of course, used by parents to pay tuition to religious schools. Because
money is fungible, the schools use those funds to pay both secular and religious
teachers salaries, build both gyms and chapels, purchase both math books and Bibles.
The schools, in other words, spend their money on both secular and religious services and
products. Accordingly, it cannot be as easily said of vouchers, as it was said of the aid
in Zobrest, that they do not relieve the parochial schools of a cost of performing
their educational function. But the response is provided by the concept of private choice.
Vouchers relieve religious schools costs only if parents choose to use them at
religious schools. In Ball, Meek, and the other cases in which the Court
has invalidated the provision of aid directly to religious schools, the aid was unmediated
by parental choice. The government officials said to the religious schools, in effect:
"Here is some educational equipment for you to use in your secular programs."
They did not say to parents, "Here are secular educational materials that you
can direct to whatever school you choose."
Witters is the best example. The Inland Empire School of the Bible, which Larry
Witters was attending and whose tuition he was paying in part with funds received from the
government, was effectively receiving public funds to carry out its essential
"educational function" a function that was unapologetically religious.
But this fact which had doomed the programs in Ball, Meek, Nyquist,
and Wolman did not render the program constitutionally suspect. The reason
is that "[a]ny aid provided under Washingtons program that ultimately flows to
religious institutions does so only as a result of the genuinely independent and private
choices of aid recipients." 474 U.S. at 487. Vouchers do not relieve schools
of their expenses so much as they fund parents freedom of choice. A voucher is not,
therefore, a "direct subsidy" because the government has no way to know whether
voucher recipients will in fact choose religious schools for their children.
A second significant issue is presented by the question whether a voucher program gives
the appearance of state "endorsement" of religion or creates a "symbolic
union" between government and religion. In Ball, for example, the Court struck
down the Grand Rapids School Districts "shared time" program, in which
public-school teachers taught certain supplemental classes for students in nonpublic
schools, because "[t]he symbolic union of church and state inherent in the provision
of secular, state-provided instruction in the religious school buildings threatens to
convey a message of state support for religion to student and to the general public."
473 U.S. at 397. The Court was of the view that a "core purpose" of the
Establishment Clause was to prevent the government from "convey[ing] a message of
government approval or disapproval of religion." 473 U.S. at 389.
Whether the "no endorsement" principle is or is not historically accurate, it
remains a theme in the Courts Establishment Clause jurisprudence, as cases dealing
with holiday displays illustrate. See Allegheny County v. ACLU, 492 U.S. 573
(1989); Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668 (1984). Justice Sandra Day OConnor,
in particular, has repeatedly stated that, in her view, the "endorsement test"
is the correct test for resolving Establishment Clause questions generally. See, e.g.,
Capitol Square Review and Advisory Board v. Pinette, 115 S. Ct. 2440, 2451 (1995)
(concurring opinion).
However, the very substance of the "endorsement test" reveals why it should
not be an obstacle to a well-drafted school voucher program. It has been emphasized
throughout this paper that to survive constitutional scrutiny under the Courts
current case law, a school-voucher plan must disburse aid according to secular, neutral
criteria, and leave it to private individuals to decide whether the aid ends up at public,
private, or religious schools. Thus, in such a plan, the government has not said
anything about religion, let alone endorsed it. The courts cannot attribute to government
the choice made by a parent to send a child to religious school. See Capitol Square,
115 S. Ct. at 2448 (opinion of Scalia, J.). The Court majority has approved of Justice
OConnors observation that "there is a crucial difference between government
speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private
speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clause protect." Board
of Education v. Mergens, 496 U.S. 226, 250 (1990). And Justice OConnor put this
principle into practice in her opinion for the majority in Agostini. See 117 S. Ct.
at 2016.
This paper has assumed, as a model, a voucher program in which government funds are
disbursed to eligible parents according to neutral, secular criteria, and the parents are
then authorized to use vouchers to pay tuition and expenses at the school of their choice
public, private, or religious. The Courts cases in particular, Nyquist
teach that in order to comply with the First Amendment, both nonpublic and public
schools must be eligible. Whether or not this teaching is sound, vouchers that could only
be redeemed at private or religious schools would almost certainly be struck down. But the
school-choice litigation currently pending in Ohio raises an interesting question: What if
eligible public schools independently choose not to participate in the program, resulting
in a voucher program that, de facto, is limited almost entirely to private schools?
Responding to a widely recognized crisis in Clevelands public schools, Ohio
enacted a scholarship/voucher program in which private and religious schools within the
Cleveland City School District, as well as public schools in districts adjacent to
Cleveland were eligible to participate. Over 50 private schools, most of them religious,
chose to participate, that is, to redeem students vouchers, but no adjacent public
school districts elected to take part in the program. See generally, Simmons-Harris v.
Goff, 1997 Ohio App. LEXIS 1766 (May 1, 1997). The programs own eligibility
criteria were completely neutral towards religion, but it turned out, because of the
public schools choices, that voucher recipients could use their vouchers to attend
only private schools, most of them religious.
Ohios Court of Appeals held that the program violated the Establishment Clause,
despite the fact that it employed neutral, secular criteria for identifying beneficiaries
and eligible schools, because "the lack of public school participation in the
scholarship program skew[ed the program] toward religion." Id.
(quoting Witters, 474 U.S. at 488). Moreover, because of this lack of public school
participation and because most of the participating private schools were religious, the
Ohio court held that "[t]he only real choice available to most parents is between
sending their child to a sectarian school and having their child remain in the troubled
Cleveland City School District. Such a choice can hardly be characterized as genuine
and independent. Rather, such a choice steers aid to sectarian schools, resulting in
what amounts to a direct government subsidy." Id. In other words, because
suburban public schools decided on their own not to participate in the Cleveland program,
the Ohio court treated the program like the program in Nyquist, where the program
was limited by its literal terms to nonpublic schools.
The Ohio Court of Appeals decision was erroneous, and this author has filed a brief in
the Ohio Supreme Court arguing that the decision should be reversed. The Ohio Court of
Appeals confused the programs neutral criteria with how other actors
those schools that chose not to participate act upon those criteria. The Court of
Appeals was also troubled by the fact that, as it turned out, most voucher recipients
ended up redeeming those vouchers at religious schools. Agostini is clearly to the
contrary. Citing both Zobrest and Mueller, the Court stated in Agostini
that the "constitutionality of an aid program [does not] depend on the number of
sectarian school students who happen to receive the otherwise neutral aid." 117 S.
Ct. at 2013.
The Ohio Court of Appeals decision was plainly incorrect, but it highlights yet another
potential obstacle to be overcome by a voucher program. The Ohio litigation suggests that
school-choice advocates would be well advised to take care, when designing a voucher
proposal, that the programs ability to offer the full range of options to parents
cannot be stymied by other actors footdragging or reluctance to participate.
This paper has discussed the application of the Supreme Courts
"Establishment Clause" jurisprudence to neutral school-voucher programs. The
underlying assumption of this discussion, and of most voucher-related litigation, is that
the constitutionality of aid to religious schools must depend on whether the First
Amendment permits such aid. Some oppose voucher and choice programs in general
even programs that exclude religious schools but it is widely accepted, even
by some leading opponents of aid to religious schools, that school-choice programs limited
to secular public schools are permissible and perhaps even desirable. Others might even
extend such programs to non-religious private schools.
One of the pioneering school-choice efforts the 1990 Milwaukee Parental Choice
Program originally included only non-religious private schools. That program
was upheld by the Wisconsin Supreme Court. Davis v. Grover, 480 N.W.2d 460 (Wis.
1992). In 1995, however, the program was expanded to include religious schools, and a
whole new round of litigation began. The Wisconsin Supreme Court was deadlocked the first
time it reviewed the expanded program, and the lawsuit is still ongoing. The Wisconsin
litigation suggests that, in the minds of many, the primary constitutional question for
school-choice advocates is whether the Establishment Clause permits the inclusion of
religious schools.
This analysis overlooks another important question of constitutional law. Does the
Constitution permit the legislature to exclude religious schools from an otherwise
generally applicable voucher program that includes public and non-religious private
schools?
This interesting and hitherto less-explored question is presented in the school-choice
cases currently pending in Vermont and Maine. In both of these States, small towns and
rural localities that lack their own public schools pay students tuition at approved
schools, including private schools, chosen by the students. This system of providing
education is called "tuitioning." In the Vermont case, one local school district
decided to "tuition" some of its students to a Catholic high school, but the
State Department of Education refused to permit it. In effect, the State seeks to require
the local school district to discriminate against religious schools. See Chittenden
Town School District v. Vermont Dept. of Education, Vermont Supreme Court Docket No.
97-275.
The Maine case presents a similar scenario. Maine has engaged in "tuitioning"
for over 200 years, and for most of this time, religious schools were eligible to
participate. In 1981, however, Maine enacted legislation excluding religious schools from
the tuitioning program. Some parents who sent their children to a Catholic high school,
which had previously been eligible for tuitioning, sued, claiming that the Constitution
prohibited the exclusion of religious schools from the program when other private schools
were included. See Bagley v. Raymond School Department, Superior Court Civil Action
Docket No. CV-97-484. In both cases, those who oppose including religious schools in the
tuitioning program cite many of the cases that have been discussed in this paper and argue
that the Establishment Clause prohibits such inclusion.
The Maine and Vermont cases present an important question one that is as
important to supporters of aid to religious schools as are the Establishment Clause
questions discussed in this paper. As it becomes increasingly clear that government-run
public schools are in need of reform and that school choice works, it can be expected that
many states, cities, and school districts will enact some kind of voucher program or
otherwise attempt to create competition in the education marketplace. It can also be
expected, however, as the Maine and Vermont cases reveal, that opponents of aid to
religious schools will seek to exclude religious schools from participating in these
reforms. Are religious schools entitled under the Constitution to be included?
Indeed, can an argument be made that the Free Exercise Clause requires recognition
of religious schools as qualified beneficiaries?
The First Amendment prohibits any law "respecting an establishment of
religion." An important corollary to this rule is that government may not
discriminate against religion. See Everson v. Board of Education, 330 U.S.
1, 18 (1947). The "Establishment Clause" works together, not at
cross-purposes, with the First Amendments "Free Exercise Clause," under
which the government may "make no law . . . prohibiting the free exercise [of
religion.]" Protection for "free exercise of religion" includes the
principle that religious practice and belief are specially privileged, and that the
government "may not . . . impose special disabilities on the basis of
religious views or religious status." Employment Div. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872,
877 (1990); see Church of Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. City of Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520,
532 (1993).
In Rosenberger v. Rectors and Visitors of the University of Virginia, 515 U.S.
819 (1995), the Supreme Court reaffirmed this principle, holding that the University of
Virginia could not single out and exclude a religious newspaper from a general program
under which student publications were funded by student fees. And in Capitol Square
Review and Advisory Board v. Pinette, 515 U.S. 753 (1995), decided the same day as Rosenberger,
the Court applied the same principle in a different context, holding that the government
could not exclude religious speech and symbols in that case, a Latin cross
from the plaza in front of the State House, given that state law made the plaza generally
available for public use and expression. The controlling constitutional principle is that
government may not single out, exclude, or discriminate against religious speech,
expression, and activity. Once government decides to permit or to encourage some
expression, it cannot exclude religious expression.
In Rosenberger and Capitol Square the government attempted to create an
open forum for expression but excluded religious speech. Supporters of aid to
religious schools should emphasize that, under these cases, the First Amendment similarly
does not permit the government to establish a "forum" for education that
excludes religious schools. This is not an argument that the government is required
to subsidize religious education. It is, rather, an argument that religious schools may
not be singled out for unfavorable treatment. A well-drafted educational-choice program
should improve education generally by allowing parents, not the government, to choose
which educational messages, including religious messages, they wish to communicate to
their children.
Over the past half-century, the Supreme Court has issued often confusing, often
contradictory decisions concerning public aid to religious schools. The Court began with
what this author believes was a sensible focus on the content or nature of the aid
provided, an approach that simply asked whether secular activities and education, as
opposed to religious indoctrination, was being funded. In the 1970s and 1980s,
however, the Court moved away from this approach, and was distracted by an increased
suspicion towards religious schools. The Court began asking not simply whether the aid was
secular, but whether there was some potential or possibility of "advancing
religion" or of creating the appearance of a government "endorsement" of
religion. During this period, the three-part Lemon test proved a formidable
obstacle to nearly all proposals to aid children in religious schools.
In the late 1980s, however, and in its most recent opinions as well, the Supreme
Court has rediscovered a theme that was present in its earliest cases, and has
increasingly focused on the role of independent private choice as a means of guaranteeing
that the government does not "establish" a religion. In these cases, the Court
has moved from examining the content of the aid program to evaluating the means
by which the aid reaches the beneficiary. It has recently upheld programs that provide
benefits to individuals under secular neutral criteria, even if those individuals then use
those benefits to support or attend religious schools. The constitutional key has been the
concept of independent private choice. At the same time, the Court has been moving away
from and even ridiculing the Lemon test. That test has frequently
been ignored, and it has seemed to many observers that the Lemon test is dead.
The Courts most recent cases suggest that a well-crafted school-choice plan can
pass constitutional muster. The Court has relied upon the model of a hypothetical
government employee who chooses to donate some of his salary to a religious charity as a
constitutional touchstone, and this model should be invoked for voucher-type programs.
Supporters of aid to religious schools should take care to draw the analogy between this
charitable-contribution model and a parents use of an educational voucher to attend
a religious school. This paper has shown that the potential constitutional difficulties
with this analogy are surmountable.
The author continues to believe that it is important to challenge Lemon v. Kurtzman
and its progeny, which disallowed forms of aid to parochial schools that were distinctly
secular in content. Just as Aguilar v. Felton was overruled, a new Court majority
may re-examine and overrule other mistaken decisions such as Lemon, Nyquist,
Meek, and Wolman. While "independent private choice" provides one
avenue for relieving the economic burden on religious schools, reconsideration of these
damaging and misguided precedents may, in the long run, provide a more satisfactory
rationale for assisting students in parochial schools with the severe economic burdens of
their secular programs.
This paper has also discussed the relevance of the Free Exercise Clause, which is at
least equal in importance to the Establishment Clause in the protection for religious
liberty afforded by the First Amendment. Not only is government permitted to include
religious schools in school-choice programs, but it may not, consistent with the First
Amendment, discriminate against religion by excluding them.
* * *
Scholars, legislators, commentators, and citizens are increasingly aware that parental
choice in education is necessary both to improve educational quality and to enhance
educational diversity. Religious schools should and will play a vital part in the future
of educational reform. The Constitution should not be read to deny to religious schools
this important role. It is best read as welcoming and appreciating their longstanding and
exemplary achievements.
|